[Note: Both reviewers recommended publication of the following essay for Paleoanthropology, but it has not yet been accepted. If you like it and want to cite it, go ahead and cite this page. I'll let you know if it ever gets officially published.]
Introduction: Physical anthropology as pseudo-taxonomy
At one time, the field
of physical anthropology was occupied primarily with establishing the number
and natures of the elementary natural units of the human species. Radical
biologists, like Ernst Haeckel (1868) , W. C. Osman Hill (1940) and Reginald R.
Ruggles Gates (1944) even held the different varieties of living peoples to be
themselves species, rejecting the familiar interbreeding criterion. Nevertheless,
once that question was resolved to everyone’s satisfaction, in the early 1960s,
(e.g., Barnicot 1963), the question still remained about how to understand the
elementary units of the human species taxonomically below the species level.
In Nature,
Campbell (1962) formally identified H.
sapiens sapiens, H. sapiens afer,
H. sapiens asiaticus, H. sapiens americanus, H. sapiens australasicus, and H. sapiens neptunianus. Concurrently, based
on serological genetic considerations, Boyd (1963) proposed thirteen human “races,”
clustered into seven “groups” in Science. Garn (1961) identified nine “geographical
races” and 32 “local races”. Coon (1962) identified five subspecies of living Homo sapiens (ignoring the additional
nonsense about their having evolved in parallel from five subspecies of Homo erectus, and its possible bearing
on school integration), namely: Caucasoids, Mongoloids, Negroids, Capoids, and
Australoids.
In the intervening decades, we stopped thinking
about and teaching about human variation that way in physical anthropology. We have learned to
talk about human variation without formal biological taxonomy. The actual
empirical biological structure of our species is “regarded as constituting a widespread network of more
or less interrelated, ecologically adapted and functional entities” (Weiner
1957: 80), or in contemporary language, a “structured metapopulation” that
defies taxonomic precision. The groups
that compose our species are created for particular purposes, and while they
may correlate with some biological patterns, they do not represent natural
divisions, but political identities. Classifying our species as Linnaeus did
turned out to be a square peg – round hole problem (Livingstone 1962). Race can
thus be modeled on the classic anthropological example of African witchcraft
(Evans-Pritchard 1937; Fields and Fields 2012), which structures people’s lives
in spite of not having any material, naturalistic existence.
Indeed, partly as a result of the historical
baggage associated with treating the human species in such a pseudo-taxonomic
fashion, we terminated physical anthropology altogether and rebranded ourselves
formally as biological anthropology. Yet even as biological anthropology, we retain
the urge to try and make sense of the ostensible lineages in our ancestry taxonomically
(e.g., Wood and Boyle, 2016; Reed et al., 2023), a daunting task that even Linnaeus
himself never faced back in the 18th century.
A popular science bestseller, Harari’s (2014) Sapiens, told readers on its back cover that
“[o]ne hundred thousand years ago, at least six different species
of humans inhabited Earth”. That, of course, might indeed be true. What are the
six species he identified 100,000 years ago? One, Homo sapiens, modern people. Fair enough, if a bit on the robust
side. Two, Homo neanderthalensis. Indeed,
according to the best genetic data thirty years ago (Krings et al. 1997); but
now the geneticists say I may have 2% Neanderthal DNA, which presumably changes
the status of Neanderthals, or the status of species, or both (Harvati and
Ackermann 2022; Weasel 2022). Three, Homo
denisova. Yet even the geneticists, who are the only people to whom it is
visible, say this is a genomic subgroup of Neanderthals (Meyer et al., 2012) – who,
as just noted, may not even be their own species in the first place. Four, Homo erectus. That is largely
uncontroversial as a taxon; but not at 100,000 years ago, unless perhaps we
regard species #6 as H. erectus.
Five, Homo floresiensis. Clearly, the
mysterious and isolated H. floresiensis
was something (Madison 2023). And six, Homo
soloensis, named for a different set of Indonesian fossils than H. floresiensis, which are generally
regarded as archaic H. sapiens
(Swisher et al., 1996) on account of their anatomical continuity with both H. erectus and H. sapiens.
All of a sudden, we
are down from “at least six different species” to humans, the hobbit, and
possibly Neanderthals. This is not to single out Harari for criticism, but
rather to note that biological anthropologists know that all of these species
are vexatious at best (e.g., Athreya and Hopkins 2021; Bae et al., 2023), while
outside of biological anthropology, the nuanced winks that generally accompany
these taxa tend to get lost.
The problem is not a
new one. Reviewing mammalian systematics in 1945, G. G. Simpson was frustrated
by the difference he encountered between paleontological and
paleoanthropological taxonomy. Since human are mammals, it stands to reason
that an expert on mammalian species should be able to make sense of extinct
hominin[1] species. Like any other
biological taxonomic enterprise, there is a proper taxonomic scheme, reflecting
a proper understanding of the fossil species in that particular evolutionary
lineage. It’s simply a matter of finding it. Some people see too few species
(lumpers), and some people see too many species (splitters), while a competent
paleontologist should produce results that are as Goldilocks found the baby
bear’s porridge: just right.
The problem, however, is not simply that everybody fancies themselves to be the baby bear; but rather, lies more fundamentally in the assumption that the elementary units in paleoanthropology and the elementary units of paleontology are equivalent. I think it is time to call that assumption into question. The units of paleontology, and of biology more generally, are different from the units of paleoanthropology, in that the latter are units in a story of our ancestors, and the ancestors are invariably sacred.
What are primate species?
A species, like a
culture or a gene, is infamously difficult to define precisely and
satisfactorily. Species appear to be units of nature of some sort, but
different kinds of units than species among plants or bacteria (Godfrey and
Marks 1991; Barraclough 2019). Nevertheless, for multicellular animals at
least, it appears to be an elemental unit of ecology, as a cell is an elemental
unit of physiology, a genotype is an elemental unit of a population genetics,
and an organism is an elemental unit of society. If we restrict ourselves just
to the more familiar mammalian and primate species, we can ideally identify
several properties possessed by a species: (1) it is composed of organisms
related to one another as either potential mates or competitors for mates, thus
bounded by the limits of a gene pool; (2) it constructs and is adapted to a
niche, filling a role in a dynamic ecosystem; (3) it has a locus in space and a
duration in time as an evolutionary lineage; and (4) it can replicate, making
more species, each slightly different from itself. Different definitions of
species, from Buffon (1753; Farber 1973) through Mayr (1942) and beyond,
highlight one or another of these features.[2]
A more recently-appreciated feature of species is that they are also units of conservation legislation, and thus partly cultural as well. That is why the number of extant primate species has risen so dramatically in recent decades, from about 170 in the mid-1980s (Richard 1985) to over 500 today (Strier 2022). It is not simply that the number of species is being taxonomically inflated, and is thus less accurate than it used to be (Rosenberger 2012); or that new species are finally being recognized, and their number is thus more accurate than it used to be (Groves 2014). In a sense, comparing the number of living primate species 35 years ago and today is simply unfair, because they are actually tabulating different things than they used to.
Hominin species seem just as vexed today as they did to Simpson back in 1945. His explanation was that the people doing the paleoanthropology were generally coming from medical anatomy, and simply didn’t understand taxonomy well enough: “much of the work on primates has been done by students who had no experience in taxonomy and who were completely incompetent to enter this field, however competent they may have been in other respects” (Simpson 1945:181). In particular, he noted, “Dart's placing of Australopithecus in a family ‘Homo-simiadae’ (1925) only served to exemplify the total ignorance of zoology so common among the special students of these higher primates (although, of course, Dart's work is excellent in his own field)” (Simpson 1945:188).
The ontology of hominin species
Suppose, however, that there are no recoverable biological species in the history of our lineage, perhaps because much of that history is occupied biologically by a structured meta-population rather than by distinct species (Pääbo 2015; Scerri et al. 2019). Perhaps because there is more at stake in identifying our ancestors than there is in identifying the ancestors of other species. Perhaps because the names themselves represent not so much biological ancestors, as anthropological ancestors.
The persistent confusion over hominin taxonomy is a result of misunderstanding the nature and existence of hominin species. It is not that there is a correct taxonomic interpretation of the fossils, which will reveal itself under the proper analytic technique. It’s that (1) this taxonomic practice is different from other ostensibly zoological taxonomic practices, by virtue of being reflexive; (2) the origin of this difference lies in the fact that it is naming and describing our own ancestors, and (3) ancestors are invariably sacred (in the broad anthropological sense of “special”, rather than in the narrower sense of “holy,” although the ancestors may of course sometimes be that too; Zerubavel 2012).
Figure 1: A notoriously sacred ancestor, Eoanthropus dawsoni, or Piltdown Man. |
Figure 2: An ancestor (STS-5 or Mrs. Ples) on a postage stamp |
Conclusion
Figure 3: Five official kinds of living people, from 1911 |
We talk today about a species Homo sapiens, and even about a subspecies, Homo sapiens sapiens, without further formal taxonomic structure, although with real and studiable patterns of biological diversity below that level. But instead of characterizing Homo sapiens europaeus as if it were a naturalistic taxon, today we ask instead why scientists thought it existed as such for two or three centuries when it actually doesn’t (Figure 3). Instead of asking how many and what the human races are, we ask how and why they get made, and what work they do. We may look similarly at the question in paleoanthropology of how hominin species get made and manipulated – without necessarily assuming that hominin species are biological things, because that is what we think our prehistory is supposed be composed of. It may be that the quest for a proper and correct taxonomy of hominin species is itself a vain one.
References
Athreya, S., & Hopkins, A. 2021. Conceptual issues in hominin taxonomy: Homo heidelbergensis and an ethnobiological reframing of species. Yearbook of Physical Anthropology, 175(Suppl. 72), 4–26.
Bae, C.J., Aiello, L.C., Hawks, J., et al. 2023. Moving
away from “the Muddle in the Middle” toward solving the Chibanian puzzle. Evolutionary Anthropology (in press). doi:10.1002/evan.22011
Barraclough,
T. G. 2019. The Evolutionary Biology of
Species. New York: Oxford University Press.
Boyd,
W. C. 1963. Genetics and the human race. Science,
140:1057-1065.
Buffon, Count de. 1753. l'Asne. In: Histoire
Naturelle, Générale et Particuliére, Vol. IV. Paris: Imprimerie Royale, pp.
337-436.
Campbell,
B. 1962. The systematics of man. Nature,
194:225-232.
Coon,
C. S. 1962. The Origin of Races. New
York: Knopf.
Dobzhansky, T. 1937. Genetics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia University Press.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. 1937. Witchcraft, Oracles,
and Magic Among the Azande. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Farber, P. L. 1972. Buffon and the concept of species.
Journal of the History of Biology, 5: 259-284.
Fields, B., and Fields, K. 2012. Racecraft: The
Soul of Inequality in American Life. New York: Verso.
Franklin,
S. 1995. Science as culture, cultures of science. Annual Review of Anthropology, 24: 163-184.
Franklin,
S., & McKinnon, S., eds. 2001. Relative
Values: Reconfiguring Kinship Studies. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Garn,
S. 1962. Races. Springfield, IL:
Charles C. Thomas.
Godfrey,
L., & Marks, J. 1991. The nature and origins of primate species. Yearbook of Physical Anthropology, 34:
39-68.
Groves,
C. P. 2014. Primate taxonomy: Inflation or real? Annual Review of Anthropology, 43: 27-36.
Harari,
Y. N. 2014. Sapiens: A Brief History of
Humankind. New York: Random House.
Harvati,
K., & Ackermann, R. R. 2022. Merging morphological and genetic evidence to
assess hybridization in Western Eurasian late Pleistocene hominins. Nature Ecology and Evolution, 6:
1573–1585.
Huxley,
T. 1863. Man's Place in Nature.
London: Williams and Norgate.
Kimbel,
W. H., & Martin, L. B., eds. 1993. Species,
Species Concepts and Primate Evolution. New York: Plenum.
Krings,
M., Stone, A., Schmitz, R. W., Krainitzki, H., Stoneking, M., & Pääbo, S.
1997. Neandertal DNA sequences and the origin of modern humans. Cell, 90:19-30.
Landau,
M. 1991. Narratives of Human Evolution.
New Haven: Yale University Press.
Lévi-Strauss, C. 1962. The Savage Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Livingstone,
F. B. 1962. On the non-existence of human races. Current Anthropology, 3, 279-281.
Madison,
P. 2023. Tug-of-War: Bones and stones as scientific objects in postcolonial
Indonesia. Isis, 114:77-98.
Mayr,
E. 1942. Systematics and the Origin of
Species. New York: Columbia University Press.
Meneganzin, A., and Bernardi, M. 2023. "Were Neanderthals and Homo sapiens ‘good species’?" Quaternary Science Reviews 303: 107975. https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1016/j.quascirev.2023.107975.
Meyer,
M., Kircher, M., Gansauge, M.-T., Li, H., Racimo, F., Mallick, S., . . . Pääbo,
S. 2012. A high-coverage
genome sequence
from an archaic Denisovan individual. Science, 338: 22-226.
Morgan,
L. H. 1871. Systems of Consanguinity and
Affinity of the Human Family. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Contributions to
Knowledge, Volume 17.
Osman
Hill, W. C. 1940. Classification of Hominidae. Nature, 146: 402-403.
Pääbo,
S. 2015. The diverse origins of the human gene pool. Nature Reviews Genetics, 16(6), 313-314.
Reed,
D. N., Raney, E., Johnson, J., Jackson, H., Virabalin, N., & Mbonu, N. 2023. Hominin nomenclature
and the importance of information systems for managing complexity in
paleoanthropology. Journal of Human
Evolution, 175, 103308.
Richard,
A. F. 1985. Primates in Nature. San
Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
Roberts,
M. F., DeVisser, E. M., & Marrant, J. P. 2021. Treacherous evidence:
Archival documents and the search for Peking Man. PaleoAnthropology, 1:98−119.
Rosenberger,
A. L. 2012. New World Monkey nightmares: Science, art, use, and abuse (?) in
platyrrhine taxonomic nomenclature. American
Journal of Primatology, 74(8), 692-695.
Scerri,
E. M. L., Chikhi, L., & Thomas, M. G. 2019. Beyond multiregional and simple
out-of-Africa models of human evolution. Nature
Ecology & Evolution, 3:1370-1372.
Schmalzer,
S. 2008. The People's Peking Man: Popular
Science and Human Identity in Twentieth-Century China. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Simpson,
G. G. 1945. The principles of classification and a classification of
mammals. Bulletin of the American Museum of Natural History, 85: 1-349.
Snow,
C. P. 1959. The Two Cultures and the
Scientific Revolution. London: Cambridge University Press.
Strier,
K. B. 2021. Primate Behavioral Ecology, 6th
ed. New York: Routledge.
Swisher,
C. C., Rink, W. J., Antón, S. C., Schwarcz, H. P., Curtis, G. H., &
Suprijo, A. (1996). Latest Homo erectus
of Java: Potential Contemporaneity with Homo
sapiens in Southeast Asia. Science,
274: 1870-1874.
Walker, J., Clinnick, D., and White, M. 2021. "We
are not alone: William King and the naming of the Neanderthals." American
Anthropologist 123 (4): 805-818.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/aman.13654.
Weasel, L. 2022. "How Neanderthals became white:
The introgression of race into contemporary human evolutionary genetics." The American Naturalist 200 (1):
129-139. https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1086/720130.
Weiner,
J. S. 1955. The Piltdown Forgery.
London: Oxford University Press.
Weiner, J. S. 1957. Physical anthropology: An
appraisal. American Scientist, 45:
79-87.
Withgott, J. 2000. "Is it “So Long, Linnaeus”?" BioScience 50: 646-651.
Wood,
B., &. Boyle, E. 2016. Hominin taxic
diversity: Fact or fantasy? American
Journal of Physical Anthropology, 159(S61): 37-78.
Zerubavel,
E. 2012. Ancestors and Relatives: Genealogy, Identity, and Community. New
York: Oxford University Press.
[1] Although I reject the two premises that led to the adoption of “hominin” (only naming clades, and privileging our genetic intimacy with the apes over our ecological difference from them), I use the term for its hipness.
[2] I regard a species to be a group of organisms composed of potential mates and competitors for mates, and representing a temporarily stable state in a biopolitical field of evolution, ecological relations, capitalism, conservation science, and governmental action.